Study GuideWeek Seven: Dualism and the Mind-Body Problem
I. Materials Assigned for the Week
II. The Central Point of This Week's MaterialMind-body dualism is the view that the mental side of a human being is not at all the same as the bodily side. That is, a human being (and maybe a few other inhabitants of the universe) are made up of two kinds of thing, rather than just one. Dualists argue that several well-known facts require a conclusion as radical as this (amongst them the fact that everything mental seems to pass Descartes' Method of Doubt test while nothing physical does). Sober sets out some of these arguments and assesses them. Putting aside their strengths or weaknesses, dualism faces one huge problem which continues to elude solution: if minds are so radically unlike bodies, how is it possible that there is such smooth causal interaction between the two as we observe in our own case? III. Other Concepts And Arguments You Are Expected To Master This Week
IV. Miscellaneous Comments and ClarificationsSober touches on each of the issues which follow. But they are so close to my heart that I have not been able to resist adding my two cents worth. (You needn't be patient) IV.A "Leibniz' Law"This is the standard philosopher's test for deciding matters of identity and non-identity. So if the issue is to decide whether minds are identical or not identical to bodies (or to certain parts of bodies like brains), then this is the test to use. How does it work? Consider a very simple example (the best sort). Suppose you know that X is a piece of chalk, and that Y is a piece of cheese: that is, Y is a not piece of chalk. In that case X must clearly be a distinct object from Y. (For if X were the very same object as Y, then one cannot be cheese and the other chalk.) Or suppose that both X and Y are pieces of chalk, but that X is longer than Y. In this case too we know there must be two pieces of chalk. (For if X were the very same object as Y, then X and Y would have to have the same length.) Or suppose that X and Y are both pieces of chalk, and in addition they are the same length; but in this case, X occupies a different spatial position from that occupied by Y. Again, X must be a distinct object from Y. (For if X were the very same object as Y, then X and Y would have to occupy the very same position.) The principle we have been appealing to in these three simple cases is this: if X has a property which Y does not have, then X is a distinct thing from Y. The same principle can be stated in a slightly different form: if X is the same thing as Y, then X has exactly the same properties that Y has. The central idea of this identity principle may seem breathtakingly obvious. But its importance can hardly be over-estimated.
Here's how to apply Leibniz' Law to decide a specific case.
Example: Take Descartes' referring terms "soul" and "mind". Here are some of the properties to be found on their property lists (abridged):
Identity of property lists. Therefore identity of things with those property lists. Souls, at least according to Descartes' theory, are identical to minds. This principle of identity is known as "Leibniz' Principle" or "Leibniz' Law" because it was first formulated in exactly this way by the seventeenth-century German philosopher and mathematician Gottfried Leibniz. Although Leibniz was the first to formulate it clearly, it was in wide-spread use long before his formulation. Plato used something like it for instance in the Republic. More to the point, Descartes certainly used it often. IV.B The General Form of Any Argument for Mind-body DualismMost of the arguments for dualism have roughly the same logical form, relying heavily on Leibniz' principle of identity. The mind has a property which no physical object has (e.g. we have privileged access to mental states); or physical objects have a property which the mind clearly lacks (e.g. an exact spatial position). This means that the property list for the mind doesn't match up entry by entry to the property list for a physical object. At least one of the properties on one of the lists isn't going to appear anywhere on the other list. Therefore, by Leibniz' Law, it follows that the mind and the body must be distinct items. Thus in its simplest form, an argument for dualism will look something like this:
Note that this is a deductive argument, not an induction or abduction. Since Leibniz' Law has to be employed in order to derive that conclusion from those premises, it is usually best to make it into an explicit premise itself. (When you are "stretching out" an argument, try to include every proposition or assumption which actually does some work in that argument. It's the unexamined, because unexpressed, assumptions which usually send things awry.) As well, especially when the properties start to get a little weird or complex, it is useful to make it explicit too that what has just been shown in the first two premises is that minds and bodies therefore have different property lists, and so are suitable for the application of Leibniz' Law. Indeed, in cases of the so-called "Intensional Fallacy" [Sober, pp. 269-270 and Week 7 IV.D below], it will be precisely this seemingly innocent step which will be up for challenge. An easy example (compare Smart, pp. 349-350):
Something has obviously gone very wrong here. But it will be impossible to figure out what if Step 4 hasn't even made explicit. More "stretching out" is obviously helpful then. Thus the canonical form you should try to set things out in:
This argument is deductively valid. It is also wonderfully simple. But some of you may have noticed that it is not all that clear that the conclusion is going to be strong enough to power full-blooded Cartesian dualism. After all, dualism is not the theory that minds and bodies are merely different things. (We can get that much from Leibniz' Law even with two differently sized pieces of chalk.) It's the theory that they are different kinds of things. (Two different pieces of chalk aren't two different kinds of anything.) According to Descartes' story, that is, the mental and the physical constitute two distinct ontological classes of things, minds and bodies belong to separate ontological categories. Again, picture God keeping a ledger of all the things that exist in the cosmos. The theory of dualism says S/he will need at least two sheets of paper, not one: one sheet for all the mental things, another completely different sheet for all the physical things. To capture this idea, we need an argument with a stronger conclusion:
This stronger conclusion is certainly strong enough to support mind-body dualism, as against mind-brain identity for instance. But now it's not so clear that the premises are strong enough to support that conclusion! (Swings and roundabouts.) Delivering on both demands - premises which are strong enough to justify their conclusion, together with a conclusion which is strong enough to support dualism - is a key issue in evaluating the plausibility of every dualist argument. IV.C First Argument for Dualism: The Argument from DoubtDescartes' "Method of Doubt" delivers the indubitability of "I exist" at the beginning of Meditation Two. But it delivers it from the indubitability of "I think" ("I am conscious") - that is, from the indubitability of a certain mental item. This is a general characteristic of the mental for Descartes: everything mental is indubitable; everything physical is dubitable. An obvious candidate for Leibniz' Law treatment. The Deception Version of Descartes' ArgumentTreat the "Evil Genius" hypothesis which Descartes introduces towards the end of Meditation One as a thought-experiment entirely on a par with thought-experiments used in physics and mathematics. So imagine an entity is intent on deceiving you in all the ways it is logically possible for you to be deceived. He can deceive you into thinking you are reading a Study Guide when you are actually gazing blankly out the window. He can make you believe that you are up and about when really you are in bed sound asleep and dreaming. He can trick you into making you feel embarrassed even when you haven't done anything embarrassing. He can fool you into thinking there is a pool of water at the end of the road when there's no water at all there, only smooth asphalt. He can make you feel confident that you remember things which never in fact happened. Indeed, he can make you think falsely about practically anything. However, there is one signal one exception to all this trickery. No matter how hard he tries, no Evil Genius can deceive you into thinking that you are thinking when really you aren't thinking. For a simple reason. In order to fool you into thinking wrongly, you would have to be doing some thinking in the first place! Now simply extend this reasoning to any mental event or operation or state. For instance, the Evil Genius will have no more success fooling me into thinking I am embarrassed when I'm not embarrassed than he has fooling me into thinking I'm thinking when I'm not thinking. He may well trick me into feeling embarrassed when there is no good reason for me to feel embarrassed (I haven't made a blue). But He can't fool me about whether I am feeling embarrassed when I am feeling embarrassed; he can't whisper persuasively in my ear: "Oh that's not embarrassment you are feeling right now, it's actually a pain in your left toe"; when I feel embarrassed, I can't be tricked into thinking I am feeling something else. According to the dualist, this is characteristic of everything mental. The Evil Genius can't make me think falsely that I'm bored out of my skull when I'm actually so excited I can hardly sit still. Neither can he fool me into believing falsely that I am feeling excitement when what I am actually feeling is boredom. When I'm any of these mental states I know I am, and that's the end of the matter. This means that there are strict limits on what it is logically possible for me to be deceived about, even by a being who has the power to deceive me in all possible ways. Such considerations deliver (or seem to deliver) a tidy argument indeed:
Everyone has heard of Descartes' stroke of genius cogito ergo sum, "I think, therefore I am". This argument is just one way of putting the cogito to the service of dualism. Obviously, it depends heavily on the element of doubt and deception introduced by the Evil Genius thought-experiment. But everything here can be put in more "neutral" terms. The Incorrigibility Version of Descartes' ArgumentJust go back to what cogito ergo sum was supposed to deliver. It was supposed to deliver the first of Descartes' "foundational" truths: "I exist". Now, what was so special about foundational truths? That they must be true no matter what the circumstances are; that they are immune from all logical possibility of error, that it is logically impossible - and not merely "technically impossible" or "circumstantially impossible" (Sober, pp. 179-180) - for us to be mistaken about them. This gives another candidate for Leibniz' Law.
A Modern Version of Descartes' Argument: The "Privileged Access" We Have to Our Own MindsThere is a more contemporary way to run the basic lesson Descartes was trying to run with talk of "the Evil Genius" and "logical possibility". Focus your attention on the question: "Why is everything mental undoubtable and everything physical doubtable?" It is because there are two entirely different methods for arriving at knowledge of factual matters and not just one. Descartes was merely the first philosopher to show us this enduring truth. But enduring truth it is, and we can use it for dualism nowadays as powerfully as before. Method One is what is sometimes called introspection. It is the method we use in order to find out whether it's regret or relief that we are feeling as someone walks out the door. It's the method we use to access what colour this curtain swatch looks and whether it looks the same colour as that book-cover. It's the method we employ when the dentist asks us whether the anaesthetic is beginning to kick in yet, and especially how we tell when it hasn't! Here are some distinguishing features of this Method One. Method Two is better called inspection or observation than introspection. It's the method which the budding doctor learns when he learns all about how to probe, palpitate and poke people. The dentist uses it to discover which teeth are rotten, regardless of whether they happen to be hurting me right now or not. It's the method by which we find out that our skin is inflamed, that our fingers are bleeding, that our glasses have a crack in them. The features of such ordinary sensory observation or inspection are familiar. What the theory of mind-body dualism wants to do with these commonplaces is simple. We are supposed to realise that not only do we have two different methods of acquiring knowledge here. As well, those methods are methods for acquiring knowledge about different kinds of things. We use introspection to access mental kinds of things. We use inspection to access physical kinds of things. This claim generates a tidy argument:
You are probably sick to death of my inserting Leibniz' Law of Identity as a separate premise in all these arguments. I do it deliberately: Leibniz' Law in these cases is sometimes attacked as a false premise! More accurately: some philosophers argue that it is false to claim Leibniz' Law applies to the properties used in such arguments as the argument from doubt. And they have a point. IV.D Criticism: Do These Arguments Commit "The Intensional Fallacy"?After all, the properties that are going on the property lists in steps 3 and 4 of the arguments above are all slightly special. They involve what are called "intensional contexts", in which we use "intensional" or "epistemological" words such as: It's not hard to find arguments which are exactly parallel to Descartes' ones, using exactly the same sorts of epistemological or intensional verbs, but which deliver ludicrously false conclusions. (Remember the "Noble Savage"?) Where these arguments go sour, the finger of blame usually points to using Leibniz' Law in circumstances where it shouldn't be used. What I believe or don't believe about X, what I know or don't know about X, what I fear or don't fear about X, and so on, should never be facts which go on thing X's property list. Rather, since each of those facts is only telling us something about me, not about the thing X in itself, if it's going to go on any item's property list, it should go on the property list for me, not for X.
The fallacy is that Leibniz' Law delivers the Conclusion only by being applied to wrongly constructed property lists in the Premises.
The epistemological verbs which make this an "intensional context" are underlined. The conclusion of this little argument is patently false; the key Premises 1 and 2 look to be just as patently true; and the logical structure seems valid enough. So where's the little stinker? There are not many places left. What's wrong is that Premise 6 is in fact false: Leibniz' Law does not apply in this case. What I know and what I do not know, especially about the drugs in my cabinet, are facts about me. They are not facts about the chemicals. So the property "known by me to relieve my headache" ought not to go on aspirin's property list (as in Restatement 3), nor should "not known by me to relieve my headache" go on acetylsalicyclic acid's property list (as in Restatement 4). Both go only on the property list for me. When Leibniz' Law is invoked at Premise 6 and the property lists for aspirin and acetylsalicylic acid are allowed to include such intensional properties, then of course the whole affair will come to grief. We have in effect allowed Leibniz' Law to deliver its judgement on the basis of improperly inflated property lists (Conclusion 5). Little wonder then that it delivers an incorrect judgement. This happens pretty obviously in the case of aspirin and acetylsalicylic acid. The very same thing happens in the case of mental states and bodily states. It's a bit harder to see the fallacy when you have Descartes' razzle-dazzle about the Evil Genius and cogito ergo sum to contend with. (Neither Descartes nor any of his contemporaries ever saw it for instance.) But it's the same basic mistake anyway. It's even more obviously a mistake if we use the chemical formula:
Whole libraries contain what I don't know about chemistry. But none of that is relevant to deciding what's what in chemistry. If a chemist determines (on the basis of their chemical property lists) that aspirin = CH3COOC6H4COOH, who am I to balk at that identity, purely on the basis that it's news to me?! A final less technical example of the intensional fallacy:
(This is the example Sober works on, pp. 269-272.) No one in her right mind wants to marry Clark Kent, the wimp of all time. But that fact is not actually a fact about Clark Kent. The fact about Clark Kent is that he behaves like a wimp when he is in his disguise as a reporter for the Daily Globe. The fact that Lois Lane doesn't want to marry a wimp is a fact about Lois Lane. So is the fact that she does want to marry a hunk. Belonging on her property list only, we can say either of two things. We can say that Leibniz' Law does apply, but that it doesn't deliver Conclusion 4 (because Premise 1 and Premise 2 don't put different properties on Superman's and on Clark Kent's property lists, since they put all the Lois Lane stuff on her property list only). Or we can say that Leibniz' Law doesn't apply, at least not in the intended way - to the intended but incorrectly inflated property lists (because Leibniz' Law never applies to property lists which include intensional properties); in which case Conclusion 4 does follow but Premise 3 is simply false. Which we say is six of one, half dozen of the other. Either way, the argument for the non-identity of Clark Kent and Superman fails to be sound. Some of you will have noticed that this is not how Sober treats his Lois Lane case. He doesn't go in for "intensional predicates", but rather "propositional attitudes". Lay these out as alternatives.
IV.E Second Argument for Dualism: The Spatial ArgumentThe spatial argument is due to Descartes and is the second discussed by Sober (pp. 272-273). The argument occurs in Meditation Six (pg. 249). Again, the basic idea is very simple. Whereas it makes sense to attribute spatial properties to bodies, it does not make sense to attribute them to minds. With each body it makes sense to ask where it is, how big it is, what volume it takes up, how densely it is crammed into the space it takes, whether its occupancy excludes anything else occupying the same spatial position, and so on. But these questions applied to the mind seem to be nonsense - unless one is already convinced that the mind is identical to the brain, or something like that. The Crude Form of the ArgumentAt its most basic, the argument looks like this:
A Less Crude Version: The Argument From DivisibilityThe argument from the divisibility of physical bodies is closely related to the argument above. (This is the form of the spatial argument actually to be found in Descartes' Meditation Six.)
Now it is true enough, of course, that we talk about our minds being divided about something, being in two minds about something, and so on. But this sort of idiom need not be taken seriously as an objection to Premise 2 of this divisibility argument. Firstly, it is not spatial division that is at issue. Secondly, when a mind is divided in the sense in which we speak of "being in two minds about something", nonetheless it is one and the same mind which is aware of the attractions of two different alternatives; we aren't literally "in two minds". A Modern Version of the Spatial ArgumentA more up-to-date form of this same line of reasoning will stress the oddness of spatial talk more strenuously. Reporting that "My anger at George is three millimetres tall" or "My regret at having to give you a mark of C is an inch to the right of my wish to see you do well on the exam" seems just plain loony, as loony as saying "Wednesday is fat" or "Colourless green ideas sleep furiously". The oddness in such cases is sometimes expressed in terms of committing a "category mistake" (an expression coined by Gilbert Ryle, pp. 278-280). Thus:
IV.F Criticism: Do These Arguments Beg the Question?Each version of the spatial argument is formally valid (the premises deductively entail the conclusion). Hence someone who denies the conclusion (that is, who does not want accept dualism) must deny one of the premises. But the first premise in each argument (the first premise is the key one) seems compelling. Has the dualist finally made their case then? Maybe. But maybe not. In a subtle way, the three arguments we have been looking at all seem to beg the question at issue. Go back to Descartes' Meditation Two:
This, and similar passages, amount to a definition of mind: The mind is that thing which has thoughts, sensations, emotions, desires, doubts. Here is the point. Unless we are covertly dragging in non-spatiality by the back-door, there is nothing in that particular definition to rule out the possibility that a mind (the thing which does the thinking, sensing, emoting, desiring, doubting) does indeed have spatial dimensions. (Compare Sober, pg. 273.) For there is nothing in that definition, nor in any of the premises of any of the spatial arguments, to rule out the possibility that brains are the things which do the thinking, sensing, emoting, desiring, doubting and the rest. If the thing which does the thinking, sensing, emoting and so on is just the brain, then the mind, on this account, would have exactly the same physical dimensions as the brain - because it would be the brain. A mind would have a spatial dimension and it would be physically divisible. We shall turn to this rival theory of mind-brain identity in Week Nine. Probably the reason Descartes doesn't twig to this, is that he keeps switching between it and a subtly different definition of mind: The mind is that thing whose existence and character is beyond all logical possibility of doubt. This item is what the Method of Doubt delivers as indubitable, incorrigible, immune to the best efforts of the Evil Genius to deceive us about and so on. Anticipating Week Nine, what will the mind-brain identity theory have to say about the mind if it is defined this way? That there is no such thing of course! And that the Method of Doubt is a rotten way of making it seem there is! See the Intensional Fallacy.
Contents Content © 2000, 2001 Massey University | Design © 2000, 2001 Alun David Bestor | Any questions? Email the webmaster |